2013년 10월 31일 목요일

[Mathew Forstater's] Tax-Driven Money: Additional Evidence from the History of Thought, Economic History, and Economic Policy (2004)

출처: Mathew Forstater, "Tax-Driven Money: Additional Evidence from the History of Thought, Economic History, and Economic Policy," Working Paper No. 35, August 2004.


※ 발췌 (excerpts):

( ... ... )

Tax-Driven Money in Classical Economics

   One of the clearest and earliest references to the idea that a state-issued currency not tied to gold or any other commodity or currency can be managed through taxation and the declaration of public receivability is the now oft-quoted passage from Adam Smith's An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations
A prince, who should enact that a certain proportion of his taxes should be paid in a paper money of a certain kind, might thereby give a certain value to this paper money; even though the term of its final discharge and redemption should depend altogether on the will of the prince. (Smith 1776: 312)
Cannan's "sidebar" (his summary of each paragraph given in the margin) for this passage reads: "A requirement that certain taxes should be paid in particular paper money might give that paper a certain value even if it was irredeemable" (ibid.; See Wray 1998 for a discussion).  We may add to this, a remark from J.B. Say's A Treatise on Political Economy, Book I, "Of the Production of Wealth," Chapter 22, "Of Signs or Representatives of Money," Section 4, "Of Paper Money," to the effect that: 
In the first place, a paper, wherewith debts can be legally, though fraudulently, discharged, derives a kind of value from that single circumstance.  Moreover, the paper-money may be made efficient to discharge the perpetually recurring claims of public taxation (Say 1803[1964]: 280)
   We get a longer discussion of the subject from J.S. Mill's Principles of Political Economy, in Book III, Chapter 13, paragraph III.13.1, "Of an inconvertible Paper Currency,":
After experience had shown that pieces of paper, of no intrinsic value, by merely bearing upon them the written profession of being equivalent to a certain number of francs, dollars, or pounds, could be made to circulate as such, and to produce all the benefit to the issuers which could have been produced by the coins which they purported to represent; governments began to think that it would be a happy device if they could appropriate to themselves this benefit, free from the condition to which individuals issuing such paper substitutes for money were subject, of giving, when required, for the sign, the thing signified.  They determined to try whether they could not emancipate themselves from this unpleasant obligation, and make paper issued by them pass for a pound, by merely calling it a pound, and ^consenting to receive it in payment of the taxes^.  And such is the influence of almost all established governments, that they have generally succeeded in attaining this object: I believe I might say they have always succeeded for a time, and the power has only been lost to them after they had compromised it by the most flagrant abuse.
In the case supposed, the functions of money are performed by a thing which derives its power for performing them solely from convention; but convention is quite sufficient to confer the power; since nothing more is needful to make a person accept anything as money, and even at any arbitrary value, than the persuasion that it will be taken from him on the same terms by others.  The only question is, what determines the value of such a currency; since it cannot be, as in the case of gold and silver (or paper exchangeable for them at pleasure), the cost of production.
We have seen, however, that even in the case of a metallic currency, the immediate agency in determining it value is its quantity.  If the quantity, instead of depending on the ordinary mercantile motives of profit and loss, could be arbitrarily fixed by the authority, the value would depend on the fiat of that authority, not on cost of production.  The quantity of a paper currency not convertible into the metals at the option of the holder, can be arbitrarily fixed; especially if the issuer is the sovereign power of the state. The value, therefore, of such a currency is entirely arbitrary. (Mill 1848: 542-543, emphasis added)
Once again, we see that many authors understood the possibility of a tax-driven currency, under certain institutional arrangements.  This is not to say that they viewed all money as such, or that they understood all the details.  But one fact seems certain: many more authors than previously believed considered the workings of a tax-driven currency.


Taxes and the Rise and Development of Capitalism: Tax-Driven Money in Marx

Marx is well-known to have commodity money in Capital and other writings.  Like many other authors, Marx also considered tax-driven money, and it was a key to the development of wage-labour and therefore the rise and development of capitalism, particularly in the colonies (see Forstater 2003b).  In the Grundrisse, Notebook I, "The Chapter on Money," Marx recognized that "Prussia has paper money of forced currency. (A reflux is secured by the obligation to pay a portion of taxes in paper.) (Marx 1857: 132).  Furthermore, Marx viewed this as part of the larger transition associated with money and the role of the State:
(To be further developed, the influence of the transformation of all relations into money relations: taxes in kind into money taxes, rent in kind into money rent, military services into mercenary troops, all personal services in general into money services, of patriachal, slave, serf and guild labour into pure wage labour.)  (Marx 1857: 146)
In the period of the rising absolutely monarchy wth its transformation of all taxes into money taxes, money indeed appears as the moloch to whom real wealth is sacrificed.  (Marx 1857: 199)
   This same theme was brought out in Capital, where Marx discussed the "primitive accumulation" necessary for capitalist development:
The different moments of primitive accumulation can be assigned in particular to Spain, Portugal, Holland, France, and England, in more or less chronological order.  These moments are systematically combined together at the end of the 17th century in England; the combination embraces the colonies, the national debt, the modern tax system, and system of protection.  These methods depend in part on brute force, for instance the colonial system.  But, they all employ the power of the state, the concentrated and organized force of society, to hasten, as in a hot-house, the process of transformation of the feudal mode of production into the capitalist mode, and to shorten the transition.  Force is the midwife of every old society which is pregnant with a new one.  It is itself an economic power.  (Marx 1990[1867]: 915-916)
And again:
The modern fiscal system, whose pivot is formed by taxes on the most necessary means of subsistence...thus contains within itself the germ of automatic progression.  Over-taxation is not an accidental occurrence, but rather a principle.  In Holland, therefore, where this system was first inaugurated, the great patriot, DeWitt, extolled it in his Maxims as the best system for making the wage-labourer submissive, frugal, industrious ... and overburdened with work.  Here, however, we are less concerned with the destructive influence it exercises on the situation of the wage-labour than the forcible expropriation, resulting from it, of peasants, artisans, in short, of all constituents of the lower middle-class.  There are two opinions about this, even among the bourgeois economists.  Its effectiveness as an expropriating agent is heightened still further by the system of protection, which forms one of its integral parts.  (Marx 1990[1867]: 921)
   Marx's understanding of the role of taxation in the creation of wage-labour expanded after 1861 during his study of the Russian peasantry and their proletarianization (White 1996: 247).  In particular, he was influenced by his leading of N. Flerovsky's The Condition of the Working Class in Russia (Flerovsky was the pseudonym of V.V. Bervi (White 1996: 247).  Marx wrote to Engels that "this is the most important book which has appeared since your Condition of the Working Class"  (White 1996: 248):
Flerovsky made it plain that ... not all Russian peasants were on the same economic level ... While rich peasants ... could earn their living entirely from the land, the poorer ones could not because 'the amount of taxes levied on the peasantry is so great that they cannot pay it without earning wages.' (While 1996: 248)
According to Flerovsky, "the main reason which compels the worker to resort to the capitalists is to pay his taxes" (White 1996: 249).  As White reports, "Marx was delighted with Flerovsky's book and as he wrote to Engles: 'What I like, among other things, in Flerovsky is his polemic against direct taxes exacted from the peasants" (White 1996: 249):
Flerovsky's book had a lasting significance for Marx's study of Russian economic development, because the picture it presented was not contradicted by any of the other sources which Marx used, and indeed, the statistical materials which he consulted served only to add substance to what Flerovsky had said. (White 1996: 249)
Marx's extensive study of the Reports of the Fiscal Commission "served to substantiate Flerovsky's opinion that the system of taxation in Russia ... was responsible for turning workers into proletarians" (White 1996: 249).

   The influence of Flerovsky seems to be present in Engels' analysis, inserted in chapter 43 of Capital, Vol. 3, where he refers to "Russian and Indian peasants succumbing to the screws of taxation":
the lands of the Russian and Indian communistic communities, which had to sell a portion of their product, and ever-growing one at that, to get money for the taxes exacted by a merciless state despotismㅡoften enough by torture. These products were sold with no regard to their costs of production, sold at the price which the dealer offered, because the peasants absolutely had to have money at the payment date. (1981[1891]: 860)
Marx's TDM-related work is interesting because it focuses on the roles that taxation and the declaration of public receivability played, not only in monetization but also the creation of wage-labor and marketization, indeed, in the development of capitalism.  The implications for the theory of the state and economic history are potentially quite significant.


Tax-Driven Money in Early Neoclassical Economics

Some of the early neoclassical authors also displayed an understanding of tax-driven money.  One of the founders of the neoclassical approach, William Stanley Jevons, in Chapter 18 of his ^Money and the Mechanism of Exchange^, "Methods of Regulating a Paper Currency" referred to "The Revenue Payments Methods.": "Inconvertible paper money may be freely issued, but an attempt may be made to keep up its value by receiving it in place of coins in the payment of taxes" (Jevons 1875: 214).

   The most elaborate discussion, however, is found in Chapter 7 of Book II of Philip H. Wicksteed's The Common Sense of Political Economy, on "Banking. Bills. Currency":
The government has, however, a further resource.  It has the means of maintaining a perpetual recurrence of persons thus desiring money at its face value, for the Government itself has more or less defined powers of taking the possessions of its subjects for public purposes, that is to say, enforcing them to contribute thereto by paying taxes.  Ultimately it requires food, clothing, shelter, and a certain amount of amusement and indulgence for its soldiers and all its officials; and it requires fire-arms, ammunition, and the like.  And in proportion to its advance in civilization it may have other and humaner purposes to fulfil.  Now, as long as gold has any application in the arts and sciences it exchanges at a certain rate with other commodities, just as oxen exchange at a certain rate against potatoes, pig-iron, or the privilege of listening, in a certain kind of seat, to a prima donna at a concert.  The Government, then, levying taxes upon the community, may say: "I shall take from you, in proportion to your resources, as a tribute to public expenses, the value of so much gold.  You may pay it to me in actual metallic gold or you may pay it to me in anything which I choose to accept in lieu of the gold.  If you do not give it me I shall take it from you, in gold or any other such articles as I can find, and which would serve my purpose, to the value of the gold.  But if you can give me a piece of paper, of my own issue, to the face value of the gold hat I am entitled to claim of you, I will accept that in payment."  Now, as these demands of the Government are recurrent, there will always be a set of persons to whom the Government paper stamped with a unit weight of gold is actually equivalent to that weight of gold itself, because it will secure immunity from requisitions to the exact extent to which the gold would secure it.  This gives to the piece of paper an actual power of doing the work that gold to its face value could do, in the way of effecting exchanges; and therefore the Government will find that the persons of whom it has made purchases, or whom it has to pay for their services, will not only be obliged to accept the paper in lieu of payments already due, and which it chooses to say that these papers discharge, but will also be willing to enter into fresh bargains with it, to supply services or to surrender things for the paper, exactly as if it were gold; as long as it is easy to find persons who, being themselves under obligation to the Government, actually find the Government promise to relinquish their claim for gold as valuable as the gold itself.  The person who pay taxes constitute a very large portion of the community and the taxes they have to pay form a very appreciable fraction of their total expenditure, and consequently a very large number of easily accessible persons actually value the paper as much as the gold up to a certain determined point, the point, to wit, of their obligations to the Government. Thus it is that a limited demand for paper, as its face value in gold, constitutes a permanent market, and furnishes a basis on which a certain amount of other transactions will be entered into.  The Government, in fact, is in a position very analogous to that of an issuing bank.  An issuing bank promises to pay gold to any one who presents its notes, and to a certain extent that promise performs the functions of the gold itself, and a certain volume of notes can be floated as long as the credit of the bank is good.  Because bank promises to pay are found to be convenient, as a means of conducting exchanges.  After this number has been floated the notes begin to be presented at the bank, and presently it has to redeem its promises as quickly as it issues them.  The limit then has been reached and the operation cannot be repeated.  After this people will decline to accept the promise of the bank in lieu of the money, or, which is the same thing, they will instantly present the promise and require its fulfillment.  The amount of notes in circulation may be maintained, but it cannot be increased. The issuing Government does not, without qualification, say that it will pay gold to any one who presents the note, but, in accepting its own notes instead of gold, it says, in effect, that it will give gold for its own notes to any ^of its own debtors^; and as long as there is a sufficient body of these debtors to vivify the circulating fluid the Government can get its promises accepted at par.  Any Government which, even for a short time, insists on paying in paper and receiving in gold, that is to say, any Government that does not honour its own issue when presented by its debtors, will find that its subjects decline to enter into voluntary contracts with it except on the gold basis; and if its paper still retains any value whatever, it will only be because of an expectation of a different state of things hereafter that gives a certain speculative value to the promise.  If fact a Government which refuses to take its own money at par has no vivifying sources to rely on except the very disreputable and rapidly exhausted one of proclaiming to debtors, and persons under contract to pay periodic sums, that they need not do so if they hold a certificate of immunity from the Government.  Such immunity will be purchased at a price determined, like all other market prices, by the stock available (qualified by the anticipations of the stocks likely to be available presently) and the nature of the services it can render.  The power, then, of Governments to make their issues do exchange work depends on their power to make a note of a certain face value do a definite amount of exchange work; and this they can effect by giving it a definite primary value to certain persons, and then keeping the issue within the corresponding limits.  It does not consist in an anomalous, and, in fact, inconvertible, power of enabling an indefinite issue to perform a definite work, and arriving at the value of each individual unit by a division sum. (Wickseed 1910: 620-622)
The pre-20th century history of economic doctrine is filled with references to and discussions of tax-driven money.  Theorists as divers as J.S, Mill, and Jevons all recognized the possibility of a State currency managed under certain institutional arrangements, that is, through taxation and declaration of public receivability (what Wray 1998 calless 'twintopt': 'that which is necessary to pay taxes').


Tax-Driven Money in 20th Century Economic Thought

Chartalism in the 20th century is associated most closely with Georg Friedrich Knapp and John Maynard Keynes (see Wray 1998).  Another important discussion of the idea can be found in Section 2 ("Principles") of Chapter 3 ('Monetary Principles") of Fred M. Taylor's Some Chapters on Money: Printed for the Use of Students in the University of Michigan:
Principle 1. Under modern conditions in most civilized countries the full and continuous circulation of any kind of money in any particular country commonly requires a measure of legal authorization from the government of that country.  (Taylor 1906: 86)
Here we have a statement that appears to be closer to a "legal," rather than "tax," brand of chartalism.  Taylor continues, however, making it clear that legal tender laws may not be enough to drive a currency:
Principle 2. Under modern conditions representative money which is not redeemable, directly or indirectly, in either standard money or goods, seems generally require, as a condition of currency, that it should be a valid tender in some important relation, e.g. payments to government.  (Taylor 1906: 89)
It is the ability to settle the tax and other obligations to the State that drives the currency.

   As the sub-title suggests, this work was specifically designed as a text-book for Taylor's students at the University of Michigan.  The discussion contains some additional insights relevant to the present discussion.  Taylor goes on to suggest that:
standard coins which fall much short of legal requirements in respect to weight will not commonly remain in circulation, unless, though short in weight, they continue to be valid tender in some important relation, particularly in payments to government.  (Taylor 1906: 90)
This insight support the thesis that even metallic currency under certain conditions can be "chartal" money.  On the other hand, acceptance at government pay offices can keep up the value of underweight coin, while on the other refusal to accept can result in a money's termination:
in repeated instances government have found it easy to expel an obnoxious money from circulation by depriving it of all legal tender status, i.e., relieving creditors of the obligation to receive it in payment of debts, and refusing to accept it for public dues.  (Tayor 1906: 90)
   The issue of acceptability was emphasized by another of the great 20th century contributors to chartalist thought, Abba Lerner. While Lerner's contributions to chartalism and functional finance have been outlined elsewhere(see Forstater 1999; 2003a), his entry on "Money" in the ^Encyclopedia Britannica^ has heretofore been overlooked:
Any particular seller will accept as money what he can use for buying things himself for settling his obligations.  This seems to say that a means of payment will be generally acceptable if it is already generally acceptable, and it looks like a circular argument. But it only means that general acceptability is not easily established.  General acceptability may come about gradually.  If a growing number of people are willing to accept payment in a particular form, this makes others willing to accept that kind of payment.  General acceptability may be established rapidly if very important sellers of creditors are willing to accept payment in a particular form of money.  For example if the government announces its readiness to accept a certain means of payment in settlement of taxes, taxpayers will be willing to accept this means of payment because they can use it to pay taxes.  Everyone else will then be willing to accept it because they can use it to buy things from the taxpayers, or pay debts to them, or to make payments to others who have to make payments to the taxpayers, and so on.  (Lerner 1946: 693)
Lerner's 1946 entry was subsequently replaced with one by Milton Friedman.

   The chartalist notion that taxes-drive-money and related ideas such as the role of taxation and the declaration of public receivability in the creation of wage-labor can be found in Classical, Marxist, early Neoclassical, and 20th century economic thought.  The claim is not that this is the only or even the predominant theory of money, but rather simply that the ideas were put forward by many more economists (and of all theoretical persuasions) than was once commonly understood.  Likewise, many more historical instances of tax-driven money can be identified.  We now turn to one particular fascinating case, the West African cowrie.


The Tax-Driven Cowrie

Chartalism forces a reconsideration of virtually all of the received wisdom coming out of traditional monetary theory and history.  The cowrie currency used in parts of Africa, for example, is often cited as an example of "primitve" money (see, e.g., Friedman 1972: 927).  A brief examination of the history of the cowrie, however, shows it to be tax-driven.  We would do well to take seriously Polanyi's admonition that "A warning is in order against the ethnocentric bias that so easily takes hold of us on economic subjects that arise outside of our own Western culture" (1966: 177):
We are used to ranging cowrie with the other shell as a sample of primitive money in a supposed evolutionary perspective of the "origins and development of money."  Historical research removes this evolutionary bias.  Cowrie currencies emerged on the Middle and Upper reaches of the Niger at a time when metal currencies and, indeed, coined money were long established in the Mediterranean heartlands.  This is the background against which the emergence of a new nonmetallic currency in Islamic West Africa should be viewed.  It will then not be erroneously regarded as part of a general evolution of money, but rather as a feature in the spread both of ^centralized government^ and of food markets in the early [African] empires which left its imprint on the local history of money  (Polanyi 1966: 178, emphasis added─Karl Polanyi 1966, Dahomey and the Slave Trade; An Analysis of an Archaic Economy, Seattle: University of Washington Press.)
   The use of cowrie as money in West Africa began between 1290 and 1352, and gold and metallic coin had long been in use prior to that time in the region (Polanyi 1966: 179-180).  According to Polanyi, "Dahomey's cowrie was definitely not primitive money" (1966: 189); rather, it is an example of "the launching of a currency as an instrument of taxation" (1966: 186).  Even the local legend regarding the cowrie's origin supports the thesis that cowrie money is a creature of the state (1966: 186).

   Evidence from other areas and authorities snow[? now] exists to support the thesis of the tax-driven cowrie.  Lovejoy reports that in precolonial Nigeria
Dependencies of such emirates as Nupe paid their levies in cowries as well, so that the taxation system effectively assured that people participated in the market economy and used the currency, a policy remarkably similar to the one which the later colonial regimes pursued in their efforts to see their own currencies accepted.  (Lovejoy 1974: 581)
Law confirms the thesis for other areas of West Africa, such as Bornu in the 19th century:
The apparent preference to the payment of taxes in moneyㅡcowries or goldㅡis especially interesting.  It must be assumed that the spread of the use of cowry shells as money in West Africa depended upon state initiativeㅡthis was certainly the case with the introduction of cowry currency in Bornu in the 1840s.  (Law 1978: 49)
   One of the factors that sustained the widespread misunderstanding of the origin and nature of the cowries was the myth that the cowrie free available in virtually unlimited quantities.  On the contrary, was not native to West Africa; the state "guarded against its proliferation by preventing shiploads from being freely imported" (Polanyi 1966: 189); and the ^stringing^ of cowries "was a monopoly of the palace" (Law 1978: 49; sell also Polanyi 1966).  This latter refers to stings of specific number of cowries, and specific numbers of strings collected in a "head" (Law 1977: 209).

   The cowrie's geographical occurrence in West Africa supports the state money thesis and refutes any evolutionary explanation: "cowrie using areas and areas where it was not accepted for payment were as if their boundaries were drawn by administrative authority" (Polanyi 1966: 190):
This was a place of multiple currencies, while Dahomey and Ashanti had succeeded in keeping their monetary systems separate in the face of what must appear to the modern mind as insuperable obstacles.  Dahomey used cowrie exclusively, in elaborate, never-changing division, maintained at an unvarying exchange rate of 32,000 cowries to one ounce of goldㅡan amazing feat.  (Polanyi 1966: 29)
The "compulsory monetization of sale-purchase" meant that nothing was available for sale except in cowrie, and there was no barter whatsoever (Polanyui 1966: 84).  It now seems likely that the cowrie was also tax-driven in other areas of the world where it served as money.  Elwin reported in 1942 that in parts of India, "There are still many of the old generation who remember the days when the cowrie was used as currency and was accepted in the payment of taxes" (Elwin 1942: 121).

   The cowrie was clearly tax-driven over most if not all of precolonial West Africa, and elsewhere.  Much more research is required, of course, but it appears that many more monies in history may have been tax-driven than was previously believed.


Tax-Driven Money in the History of Economic Policy: The Case of John C. Calhoun

   In addition to tax-driven money in the history of economic thought and economic history, the idea can be found in the history of policy discussions.  One interesting instance is the case of John C. Calhoun, a U.S. Senator and Vice President of the United States of American in the 19th century.  In several speeches in the U.S. Senate in the 1830s, Calhoun spoke of the idea and made references to a number of additional historical cases.

   In an 1838 speech in reply to Daniel Webster on the Subtreasury bill, Calhoun argued that:
I now undertake to affirm positively, and without the least fear that I can be answered, what heretofore I have but suggested-that a paper issued by the government, with the simple promise to receive it in all its dues ..., would, to the extent that it would circulate, form a perfect paper-circulation. (1981[1831]: 220)
Earlier, in 1837, in a speech on a bill authorizing the issue of treasury notes, Calhoun cited the case of North Carolina in support of a tax-driven currency:
North Carolina, just after the Revolution, issued a large amount of paper, which was made receivable in dues to her.  It was also made a legal tender; which, of course, was not obligatory after the adoption of the federal constitution.  A large amount, say between four an five hundred thousand dollars, remained in circulation after that period, and continued to circulate for more than twenty years at par with gold and silver the whole time, with no other advantage than being received in the revenue of the State, which was much less than one hundred thousand dollars per annum.  (Calhoun 1980[1837]: 566)
In a speech the next month on his amendment to separate the government and the banks, Calhoun added the case of Russia:
We are told there is no instance of a government paper that did not depreciate.  In reply, I affirm that there is none assuming the form I propose [notes receivable by government in payment of dues] that ever did depreciate.  Whenever a paper receivable in the dues of government had anything like a fair trial, it has succeeded.  Instance the case of North Carolina referred to in my opening remarks.  The drafts of the treasury at this moment, with all their incumbrance, are nearly par with gold and silver; and I might add the instance alluded to by the distinguished senator from Kentucky [Henry Clay], in which he admits, that as soon as the excess of the issues of the Commonwealth Bank of Kentucky were reduced to the proper points, its notes rose to par.  The case of Russia might also be mentioned.  In 1827 she had a fixed paper-circulation in the form of bank-notes, but which were inconvertible, of upward of $120,000,000, estimated in the metallic ruble, and which had for years remained without fluctuation; having nothing to sustain it but that it was received in the dues of government, and that, too, with a revenue of only about $90,000,000 annually.  (Calhoun 1980[1837]: 607)
Both Calhoun's ideas and the cases he identifies must be subject to further investigation.  It is clear from his remarks, however, that he was speaking of the advantages of a tax-driven currency.


Tax-Driven Money in Contemporary Thought: Walrasian Neoclassical and Interdisciplinary Occurrences

There are a number of interesting contemporary occurrences of TDM view, in both orthodox neoclassical economics, as well as works in political science and history.  In neoclassical economics, there has long been a question of the place of money within the modern Walrasian general equilibrium framework.  In a 1974 paper in ^Econometrica^ that even cites Lerner's 1947 article, Starr investigates the "possibility of the price of money being zero in equilibrium and the role of taxes (payable in money) in preventing a zero price" (1974: 45).
How can we eliminate the possibility of the price of money being zero in equilibrium?  In order to do this we must arrange that there be a positive excess demand for money when the price of money is zero.  One way to achieve this is to guarantee that money can always be used in payment of taxes ... Taxes can be used to create a demand for money independent of its usefulness as a medium of exchange, thereby ensuring that its price will not fall to zero. (1974: 46)

More recently, Starr has similarly argued that "Government issued fiat money has a positive equilibrium value from its acceptability for tax payments" (2003: 455: see also, Starr 2002a; 2002b).

   Harvard University political scientist David Woodruff argues that a chartalist perspective assists in the understanding of recent economic events in Russia and Argentina. In ^Money Unmade^ (1999), Woodruff uses the chartalist framework to understand the ruble's decline, Woodruff employs his chartalist-inspired "institutional-sociological" approach to money to look at the spread of "monetary surrogates" in Argentina after going off the dollar-peg (Woodrugg, forthcoming).

   Recent work by UCLA historian Richard von Glahn discusses the chartalist (he uses "cartalist") monetary theorists of early modern China.  In Fountain of Fortune (1996), Von Glahn documents state monetary policies from the Song, Ming, and Qing dynasties, and the theoretical traditions that informed them and through which they may be understood.  As Von Glahn's work makes clear, the debate between the chartalists and the metallists is not unique to the West.


Conclusion

The notion of tax-driven money can be found throughout the history of economic thought, in the works of a remarkable range of authors representing various time periods and schools of thought.  The idea also appears in policy discussions and in fields outside economics, such as political science and history.  Neither is the idea unique to the West, as Von Glahn's work demonstragtes.  It also appears that monies previously thought to be "primitive", such as the cowrie, were actually tax-driven.  Nevertheless, the idea is conspicuously absent from textbooks and works on monetary theory and history.

   One possible explanation for the silence concerning the notion may have something to do with the implications of the TDM idea for the relation of the economy and the state.  Orthodox and even many heterodox approaches view the economy as relatively 'autonomous' and theory often assumes a 'pure' economy with no government.  The TDM perspective implies that not only is money a creature of the state, but that much else about the economy is as well.  The traditional distinction between "endogenous" and "exogenous" factors may need to be re-examined, or even discarded.  There may, then, also be important methodological implications of the TDM view.  More research needs to be conducted in all these areas.

References: ( ... )

2013년 10월 26일 토요일

[Pavlina R. Tcherneva's] Chartalism and the tax-driven approach to money (2006)

출처: Philip Arestis, Malcolm C. Sawyer (eds), A Handbook of Alternative Monetary Economics (Edward Elgar 2006)

※ 발췌 (excerpt):

* * *

Chapter 5. Chartalism and the tax-driven approach to money

By Pavlina R. Tcherneva *

n*. Helpful comments by Matthew Forstater, John Henry and Warren Mosler are gratefully acknowldged.

1. Introduction

Economists, numismatists, sociologists and anthropologists alike have long probed the vexing question 'What is money?'  And it seems Keynes's 'Babylonian madness' has infected a new generation of scholars unsettled by the conventional accounts of the origins, nature and role of money.[n1]  Among them are the advocates of a heterodox approach identified as 'Chartalism', 'neo-Chartalism', 'tax-driven money', 'modern money', or 'money as a creature of the state'.
[n1] In a paper of the same title, Ingham recounts what Keynes referred to as his 'Babylonian madness'.  In a letter to Lydia Lopokova, Keynes wrote that endeavouring to locate the true origins of money in ancient Near East civilizations, he 'became absorbed to the point of frenzy' (Ingham, 2000: 16, n. 3).
   The Chartalist contribution turns on the recognition that money cannot be appropriately studied in isolation from the powers of the stateㅡbe it modern nation-states or ancient governing bodies.  It thus offers a view diametrically opposed to that of orthodox theory, where money spontaneously emerges as a medium of exchange from the attempts of enterprising individuals to minimize the transactions const of barter.  That standard story deems money to be neutralㅡa veil, a simple medium of exchange, which lubricates markets and derives its value from its metallic content.

   Chartalism, on the other hand, posits that money (broadly speaking) is a unit of account, designated by a public authority for the codification of social debt obligations.  More specifically, in the modern world, this debt relation is between the population and the nation-state in the form of a tax-liability.  Thus money is a creature of the state and a tax credit for extinguishing this debt.  If money is to be considered a veil at all, it is a veil of the historically specific nature of these debt relationships.  Therefore, Chartalism insists on a historically grounded and socially embedded analysis of money.

   This chapter distinguishes between several broad Chartalist propositions about the origin, nature and role of money, and several specific propositions about money in the modern context.  It offers only a cursory examination of the historical record to illuminate the essential characteristics of money emphasized in the Chartalist tradition.  Chartalist ideas are not new, although they are most closely associated with the writings of Georg Friedrich Knapp of the German Historical School. Thus the chapter briefly surveys instances in the history of thought which have emphasized the chartal nature of money.  The paper then expound on Chartalism, clarifying aspects of the concepts and drawing out the implications for modern currencies.  It concludes with a discussion of the various applications of this approach to policy.


Chartalism: the broad propositions

The historical record suggests an examination of Chartalism according to its broad and specific propositions.  The latter address the nature of money in the modern context, and although Chartalism should not be narrowly identified with the modern money approach, the specific propositions are more important for understanding today's economies, modern currencies, and government monetary and fiscal policy.

   Very briefly, the broad propositions of Chartalism are:

1. The atomistic view of money emerging as a medium of exchange to minimize transactions costs of barter among utlility-maximizing individuals finds no support in the historical record.

2. The appropriate context for the study of money is cultural and institutional, with special emphasis on social and political considerations.

3. Consequently, Chartalists locate the origins of money in the public sector, however broadly defined.

4. In its very nature money is a social relation of a particular kindㅡit is a credit-debt relationship.

5. Chartalism offers a stratified view of social debt relationships where definitive money (the liability of the ruling body) sits at the top of the hierarchy.

6. Money functions first and foremost, as an abstract unit of account, which is then used as a means of account and the settling of debt.  Silver, paper, gold or whatever 'thing' serves as a medium of exchange is only the empirical manifestation of what is essentially a state-administered unit of account.  Thus the function of money as a medium of exchange is incidental to an contingent on its first two functions as a unit of account and a means of payment.

7. From here, as Ingham aptly put it, money of account is 'logically anterior and historically prior to market exchange' (2004: 25)


Neo-Chartalism: the specific propositions

The recent revival of the Chartalist tradition, also dubbed neo-chartalism, tax-driven money, or the modern money approach is particularly concerned with understanding modern currencies.  Thus contemporary Chartalists advance several specific propositions about money in the modern world:

1. Modern currencies exist within the context of certain state powers.  The two essential powers are:
(a) the power to levy taxes on its subjects, and
(b) the power to declare what it will accept in payment of taxes.

2. Thus the state delimits money to be that which will be accepted at government pay offices for extinguishing debt to the state.

3. The purpose of taxation is not to finance government spending but to create demand for the currencyㅡhence the therm 'tax-driven money;/

4. Logically, and in practice, government spending comes ^prior^ to taxation, to provide that which is necessary to pay taxes.

5. In the modern world, states usually have monopoly power over the issue of their currency.  States with sovereign currency control (i.e. which do not operate under the restriction of fixed exchange rates, dollarization, monetary unions or currency boards) do not face any operational financial constraints (although they may face political constraints) [n2]
[n2] Chartalism is not limited to floating exchange rate systemㅡ'even a gold standard can be a Chartalist system' (Wray 2001: 1).  The choice of exchange rate regime has various implications for state spending power, but it does not mean that the state has lost the ability to levy a tax on its subjects and declare how this tax will be paid.
6. Nations that issue their own currency have no imperative to borrow or tax to finance spending. While taxes creates demand for the currency, borrowing is an ^ex ante^ interest rate maintenance operation.  This leads to dramatically different policy conclusions.

7. As a monopolist over its currency, the state also has the power to set prices, which include both the interest rate and how the currency exchanges for other goods and services.

Neo-Chartalism is appropriately subsumed under the broad Chartalist school of thought.  When it is said that 'money is a creature of the state' or that 'taxes drive money', two things are important to keep in mind.  First, 'state' refers not just to modern nation-states, but also to any governing authority such as a sovereign government, ancient palace, priest, temple, or a colonial governor.  Second, 'tax' denotes not just modern income, estate or other head tax, but also any non-reciprocal obligation to that governing authorityㅡcompulsory fines, fees, dues, tributes, taxes and other obligations.

   Before detailing the broad and specific propositions of Chartalism, the next two sections take a cursory look at the historical record of the origins of money and the recognition of the chartal nature of money in the history of thought.


2. History of money

Chartalists insists on a socially embedded and historically grounded study of money.  While a conclusive chronicle of its genesis is perhaps impossible to attain, they turn to a historically informed analysis to unearth a more accurate account of the nature, origin and role of money. [n3]
[n3] A detailed analysis of the history of money is beyond the scope of this chapter.  Interested readers are directed to Chapter 1 by Tymoigne and Wray of the present volume.
Genesis of money

It is well-established fact that money pre-dated minting by nearly 3000 years.  Thus Chartalists aim to correct a common error of conflating the origins of money with the origins of coinage (Innes 1913: 394; Knapp 1924: 1; Hudson 2003: 40).

   Very generally, they advance two accounts of money's origins. Grierson (1977), Goodhart (1998) and Wray (2001) posit that money originated in ancient penal systems which instituted compensation schedules of fines, similar to wergid, as a means of settling one's debt for inflicted wrongdoing to the injured party.  These debts were settled according to a complex system of disbursements, which were eventually centralized into payments to the state for crimes.  Subsequently, the public authority added various other fines, dues, fees and taxes to the list of compulsory obligations of the population.

   The second account offered by Hudson (2003), and supported by some Assyriologist scholars (ibid.: 45, n. 3), traces the origins of money to the Mesopotamian temples and palaces, which developed an elaborate system of internal accounting of credits and debts.  The large public institutions played a key role in establishing a general unit of account and store of value (initially for internal record keeping but also for administering prices).  Hudson argues that money evolved through public institutions as standardized weight, independently from the practice of injury payments.

   These stories are not mutually exclusive. As Ingham speculates, since a system of debts for social transgressions existed in pre-Mesopotamian societies, it is highly likely that 'the calculation of social obligations was transformed into a means of measuring the equivalencies between commodities' (2004: 91).  Henry's analysis of ancient Egypt (2004) bridges the two accounts.  In Egypt, as in Mesopotamia, money emerged from the necessity of the ruling class to maintain accounts of agricultural crops and accumulated surpluses, but it also served as a means o accounting for payment of levies, foreign tribute, and tribal obligations to the kings and priests. [n4]
[n4] Henry further adds that money cannot exists without power and authority. Societies based on hospitality and exchange simply had no use for it, while in a stratified society the ruling class is compelled to devise standard units of account, which measure not only the economic surplus collected in the form of taxes, but also the royal gifts and religious dues that were imposed on the underlying population (2004: 90).
   The importance of the historical record is: (1) to delineate the nature of money as a social debt relationship; (2) to stress the role of public institutions in establishing a standard unit of account by codifying accounting schemes and price lists; and (3) to show that in all cases money was a pre-market phenomenon, representing initially an abstract unit of account and means of payment, and only later a generalized medium of exchange.


The chartality of money

The above discussion gives a preliminary indication of the chartal nature of money.  History reveals the role of the public authority in establishing a universal equivalent for measuring debts and in determining what 'thing' will be used to correspond to this accounting measure.

   As Knapp explains, payments are always measured in units of value (1973[1924]: 7-8).  Money then is chartal because the state makes a 'proclamation ... that a piece of such and such a description shall be valid as so many units of value' (ibid.: 30).  And it is besides the point what material will be used to correspond to those units of value.  Money is a 'ticket' or 'token' used as a means of payment or measure of value.  The means of payment, 'whether coins or warrants' or any 'object made of a worthless material', is a 'sign-bearing object' to which '[state] ordinance gives a use independent of its material' (ibid.: 32).

   This what gives Chartalism its name: 'Perhaps the Latin word "Charta" can bear the sense of ticket or token ... Our means of payment have this token, or Chartal, form' (ibid.).  Hereafter, Knapp defines money to always be a 'Chartal means of payment' (ibid.: 38).

   It is important to distinguish between the 'money of account' and the 'money-thing', i.e., between the abstract unit of account and the physical object that corresponds to it.  Keynes explains: 'money-of-account is the description or title and the money is the thing which answers to the description' (Keynes 1930: 3-4, original emphasis).  Orthodox theories fail to differentiate the money of account from the empirical object that serves as money, leading to several irresolvable conundrums of monetary theory (see below).

   Finally, 'definitive' money is that which is accepted at state pay offices: 'chartality has developed ... for the State says that the pieces have such and such an appearance and that their validity is fixed by proclamation' (Knapp, 1973[1924]: 36).  Keynes similarly argues that 'the Age of Chartalist or State money was reached when the State claimed the right to declare what thing should answer as money to the currency money-of-accountㅡwhen it claims the right not only to enforce the dictionary but also to weite the dictionary' (Keynes 1930: 5).

   From Mesopotamia and Egypt to modern economies, rulers, governors and nation-states have always 'written dictionary'.  Chartalism is thus able to explain why seemingly worthless objects such as tally sticks, clay tablets or paper have been used to serve as money. [n5] Governing authorities have not only picked the money of account and declared what 'thing' will answer as money, but they have also used taxation as a vehicle for launching new currencies.  This is perhaps nowhere clearer than in the cases of colonial Africa.
[n5] The case of Egypt is particularly interesting because the official unit of account called the deben, had no relation to any specific object.  It was an abstract weight measure equalling 92 grams, whereby various 'things'ㅡwheat, copper, or silverㅡequivalent to 92 g, and multiples thereof, served as money (Henry, 2004: 92).
African economies were monetized by imposing taxes and insisting on payment of taxes with the European currency.  The experience of paying taxes was not new to Africa. What was new was the requirement that the taxes be paid in European currency.  Compulsory payment of taxes in European currency was a critical measure in the monetization of African economies as well as the spread of wage labour. (Ake, 1981: 34)
Money taxes [in Africa] were introduced on numerous itemsㅡcattle, land, houses, and the people themselves.  Money to pay taxes was go by growing cash crops or working on European farms or in their mines.  (Rodney 1972: 165, original emphasis)
The tax requirement payable in European currency was all that was needed for the colonized tribes to start using the new money.  Taxation compelled the community's members to sell goods and services to the colonizers in return for the currency that would discharge their tax obligation.  Taxation turned out to be a highly effective means of coercing Africans to enter cash crop production and to offer their labour for sale (see also Forstater 2005).

   Public authorities, like colonial governors, not only 'wrote the dictionary' but also did so for many millennia.  As Keynes pointed out, money has been chartal money for at least 4000 years:
The State, therefore, comes in first of all as the authority of law which enforces the payment of the thing which corresponds to the name or description in the contract.  But it comes doubly when, in addition, it claims the right to determine and declare ^what thing^ correspond to the name, an to vary its declaration from time to timeㅡwhen, that is to say it claims the right to re-edit the dictionary.  This right is claimed by all modern State and has been so claimed for some 4000 years at least.  It is when this stage in the evolution of Money has been reached that Knapp's Chartalismㅡthe doctrine that money is peculiarly a creation of the Stateㅡis fully realized. ... To-day all civilized money is, beyond the possibility of dispute, Chartalist.  (Keynes 1930: 4-5)

3. Chartal money in the history of thought

Many scholars, both orthodox and heterodox, have dealt with the chartal nature of money.  Wray (1998) and Forstater (2006) have documented these instances in the history of thought.  Their surveys seem to indicate two separate lines of research:

1. The first uses the chartal nature of money to identify its role in the evolution of markets (Ingham, Henry), the introduction of new currencies, the spread of centralized governments (Polanyi, Lovejoy), and the emergence of capitalism and wage labour (Marx, Ake).

2. The second detects the tax-driven nature of money in its attempts to discover why seemingly worthless paper circulates as a medium of exchange (Smith, Say, Mill, Wicksteed).
CF. Forstater, M. (2006). 'Tax-driven money: Additional evidence from the history of thought, economic history, and economic policy', in M. Setterfield (ed.), Complexity, Endogenous Money, and Exogenous Interest Rates, Cheltenham, UK and Northhampton, MA, USA: Edward Elgar.
CF. Forstater, M. (2005), 'Taxation and primitive accumulation: in the case of colonial Africa,' ^Research in Political Economy^, 22, 51-64. 
From the first group of scholars, for example, Polanyi clearly rejects the traditional treatment of cowrie shells as 'primitive money' (Forstater 2006).  In studying the introduction of non-metallic money in Africa, Polanyi observes that cowrie existed alongside metal currencies, which were already well established in the continent.  The cowrie was, in fact, an example of 'the launching of a currency as an instrument of taxation' (1966: 189, quoted in Forstater 2006).  Polanyi furthermore argues that the emergence of non-metallic currencies should be correctly regarded 'as a feature in the spread both of ^centralized government^ and of food markets in the early [African] empires which left its imprint on the local history of money' (ibid.).

   Lovejoy (as Ake and Rodney above) similarly reports that taxation in pre-colonial Nigeria was used to generate demand for new currencies:
emirates [of Nigeria] paid their levies in cowries as well, so that the taxation system effectively assured that people participated in the market economy and used the currency, a policy remarkably similar to the one which the later colonial regimes pursued in their efforts to see their own currencies accepted. (Lovejoy 1974: 581, quoted in Forstater 2006).
Marx also wrote on the tax imperative behind modern money, but his focus was on its role in the rise of capitalism and wage-labour. It is well known that Marx had a commodity theory of money, but he none the less emphasized that money relations obfuscate the underlying social relations of production. (Ingham 2004: 61). This, Forstate argues, played a key role in Marx's emphasis on the role of taxation and the state in monetizing primitive economies and accelerating the accumulation of capital (see detailed analysis in Forstater 2006).  The transformation of all taxes into money taxes has led to the transformation of all labour into wage labour, much like the African colonial experience above (Marx, 1857─Grundrisse: Foundations of the Critique of Political Economy, New York: Vintage.)

   The second group of scholars who had contemplated the idea of tax-driven money were those concerned with the value of money and those who attempted to solve the (neo)classical riddle, why certain units of seemingly useless material circulate as a medium of exchange while others, of apparent worth, do not.

   One need not look further than Adam Smith's Wealth of Nations for acknowledgement of the chartal nature of money and the role of taxation.[n6]
A prince, who should enact that a certain proportion of his taxes should be paid in a paper money of a certain kind, might thereby give a certain value to this paper money; even though the term of its final discharge and redemption should depend altogether on the will of the prince. (Smith 1776: p. 312)
[n6] For a detailed discussion of Smith's position, see Wray (1998): pp. 19-23 and Wray (2000): pp. 47-9.
Forstater reports that Say and Mill too recognized that paper had value because it was 'made efficient to discharge the perpetually recurring claims of public taxation' (Say 1964[1880]: 280, quoted in Forstater 2006) and because the state had consented 'to receive it in payment of taxes' (Mill 1848: 542-3, quoted in Forstater 2006).  Mill further added that, if the issuer is the sovereign state, it can arbitrarily fix the quantity and value of paper currency (ibid.).  Mill here seems to acknowledge the Chartalist claim that the sovereign state, in effect, 'writes the dictionary' by picking the unit of account and arbitrarily fixing its value.  Finally, Wickseed explicitly acknowledged the role of taxation as a method of creating a perpetual desire for money so that the government could acquire all goods and service necessary for its official and other purposes (Wickseed, quoted in Forstater 2006).

   While the tax-driven money approach finds some support in the history of economic thought, simple recognition of the tax imperative behind the money was not sufficient to draw out the full implications and logical extensions behind the chartality of money.  Clearly neoclassical economists struggled to understand the use of paper money, but the tax-driven nature of money simply did not square with the traditional view of money as a veil.  Thus, the next section recaps the Chartalist position by means of comparison with orthodox story orㅡas Knapp (1973[1924] and Goodhart (1998) call itㅡthe Metallist position.


4. Metallism vs Chartalism

Some of the differences between Metallism and Chartalism (M-theory and C-theory respectively [Goodhard 1998]) have already surfaced in the previous sections.  The traditional story of the origins, nature and role of money is all too familiar. According to M-theory, markets formed first as a result of individuals' inherent disposition for exchange.  Over time, money naturally emerged to lubricate these markets by dramatically reducing transactions costs.

   M-theory focuses on money as a medium of exchange.  Its ^value^ stems from the intrinsic properties of the commodity that backs itㅡusually a type of precious metal (and hence the term Metallism).  Money owes its ^existence^ to rational agents who spontaneously pick a commodity for exchange, pressed by the requirements of the double coincidence of wants (Goodhart 1998: 410).  Money, therefore, ^originates^ in the private sector and only exists to facilitate market transactions.  Because money has no special properties that endow it with a principal role, monetary analysis takes a backseat to 'real' analysis.

   Since orthodox analysis turns of the smooth functioning of private markets, it generally abstracts from the role (or intervention) of government.  The absence of any link between state and money also explains why M-theory cannot account for the important and almost universal 'one nation-one currency' relationship (Goodhart 1998).  Metallism struggles to find value in modern fiat money, no longer backed by any commodity of intrinsic worth.  For M-theory, paper currency circulates because governments have usurped control over money and because it continues to reduce transactions costs of barter (Goodhart 1998: 417. n. 21).

   Chartalism find several problems with the Metallist story.  Specifically, they identify two circular arguments, which pertain to the use of money as a medium of exchange, means of payment and store of abstract value.  The first deals with money's existence.  For M-theory, money is a consequence of rational agents 'holding the most tradeable commodity in a barter economy' (Ingham 2000: 20).  In other words: (a) money is universal because rational agents use it; and (b) rational agents use it because it is universal.  Attempts to resolve this circularity by concentrating on money's role in reducing transactions costs have been unsatisfactory.

   The logical difficulties emerge from the ‘identification problem’ㅡbenefits from using a particular commodity as medium of exchange can be recognized only after that commodity has already been in use.  Coins, for example, must be minted and circulated before the benefits of reduced transactions costs are recognized.  And, as Goodhart notes, the costs of using an unworked precious metal can themselves be quite high (1998: 411).  Thus the argument that private agents collectively and spontaneously choose a certain commodity for exchange because it reduces costs is, at a minimum, tenuous.

   The second circular argument pertains to the other functions of money.  Orthodox reasoning is that: (a) money is a store of abstract value because it is a means of payment; and (b) it is a means of payment because it is a store of abstract value (Ingham 2000: 21).  Essentially, there is no ^definitive^ property that gives money its special status.  In the absence of an unambiguous condition that explains the use of gold, wooden sticks or salt as money, spontaneous choice becomes essential to the orthodox story and it must be assued a priori.  The result is a 'helicopter drop' theory of money (Cottrell, 1994: 590, n.2─‘Post-Keynesian monetary economics,’ Cambridge Journal of Economics, 18, 587–605.).

   C-theory does not suffer from the 'identification problem' or the 'spontaneous choice' paradox.  It has no difficulty explaining the introduction and circulation of fiat currency or the 'one nation-one currency' regularity.  This is because the origin of money is located outside private markets and rests within the complex web of social (debt) relations where the state has a principal role.[n7]
[n7] This does not mean that the private sector cannot or has not created money (Goodhart 1998: 418).  The point is that the explanations of money's origin, which rest on the role of the state, are empirically more compelling.

   The legitimate and sovereign powers of the government body render money 'a creature of the state' (Lerner 1947).  Its ^value^ stems from the power of money-issuing authority.  There is nothing spontaneous about its existence; rather, it is contingent on what the state has declared to accept in payment of taxes, fees and dues at public offices.  Various 'money-things' have dominated private markets because they have been chosen for acceptation at government pay offices for settling of debt.  Chartalists avoid circular reasoning by pointing out that money's role as a unit of account preceded its role as a means of payment and a medium of exchange.  This role was instituted by the state's capacity to denominate price lists and debt contracts into the elected unit of account.


5. Acceptation: legal tender or the hierarchy of debt?

Before elaborating on Chartalist theory and its application to policy, one additional clarification is in order.  It is commonly believed that the chartal nature of money rests within the power of the state to administer legal tender laws (Schumpeter 1954: 1090).  But when Knapp claimed that 'money is a creature of law' (1973[1924]: 1), he did ^not^ propose that 'money is a creature of legal tender law', and in fact he explicitly rejected such an interpretation.  Chartalists argue that acceptation depends not on the legal tender status of money but on the stratified order of social debt relationships.  The power to delegate taxes and determine how they will be paid explains why state money is the ^most acceptable^ form of debt.

   If money is debt, clearly anyone can issue money (Minsky 1986: 228). Minsky stressed that, as a balance sheet item, money is an asset to the holder and a liability to the issuer.  What is important, however, is not the capacity to create debt but the ability to induce someone else to hold it. (ibid.).  In a sense, debt becomes money only ^after^ acceptation has occurred (Bell 2001: 151─‘The role of the state and the hierarchy of money’, CJE).  Different monies have varied degrees of acceptability, which suggests a hierarchical ordering of debts (Minsky 1986; Wray 1990; Bell 2001).

   If social debt relationships are organized in a pyramidal fashion, then the least acceptable forms of money are at the bottom of the pyramid, while the most acceptable ones are at the top (see Bell 2001).  Furthermore, each liability  is convertible into a higher and more acceptable form of debt.  What liability, then, sits at the top of the pyramid?

   To settle debts, all economic agents except one, the state, are always required to deliver a third party's IOU, or something outside the credit-debt relationship.  Since only the sovereign can deliver its own IOU to settle debts, its promise sits at the top of the pyramid.  The only thing the state is 'liable for' is to accept its own IOU at public pay offices (Wray 2003a; 146, n. 9). [n8]
[n8] For example, to be accepted, household or firm IOUs must at least be convertible into deposits (bank money) or cash (state money).  Likewise, bank deposits must necessarily be convertible into reserves or cash (state high-powered money) to be accepted.  State money is always at the end of the convertibility chain.
   This stratified view of social debt relationships provides a preliminary indication of the primacy of state currency.  But can agents simply refuse to take the sovereign's money and, therefore, undermine its position in the pyramid? The answer is 'no', because as long as there is someone in the economy who is required to pay taxes denominated in the state's currency, that money will always be accepted.

   This indicates that the ^emission^ of currency is not an essential power of the state.  In fact it has a contingent character.  The state may very well declare that it will accept payment of taxes in, say, cowries, or wooden sticks.  Indeed, such historical examples exist, although generally sovereigns have preferred to use their own stamp or paper or something over which they possess full and unconditional control.  The essence of the state money lies neither in the ability to create laws, nor in the ability to print money, but in the ability of the government to create ‘the promise of the last resort’ (Ingham 2000: 29, emphasis added),  that is, to levy taxes and declare what will be accepted at pay offices for extinguishing debt to the state.  The unit of account that settles tax obligations is delimited by the special authority, which 'does the counting' (ibid.: 22).

   Knapp himself emphasized this point: 'Nor can legal tender be taken as the test, for in monetary systems there are frequently kinds of money which are not legal tender ... but ^acceptation^ ... is decisive.  State acceptation delimits the monetary systems' (Knapp 1973[1924]: 95, original emphasis); and Keynes endorsed it: 'Knapp accepts as "Money"ㅡrightly, I thinkㅡanything which the State undertakes to accept at its pay-offices, whether or not it is declared legal-tender between citizens' (Keynes 1930: 6, n. 1).  Legal code is only a manifestation of state powers. Lack of legal tender laws does not mean that state money is unacceptableㅡsuch is the case in the European Union, for example, where no formal legal tender laws exist, yet the euro circulates widely? [n9]
[n9] Note also that a violation of the 'one nation-one currency' regularity does not mean that the state has lost the power to tax and declare what will extinguish tax obligations. In the case of currency boards, for example, the state has willingly abandoned sovereign control over its own currency in favour of a foreign monetary unit but, as long as the domestic currency is demanded for payment of taxes, it will circulate.  In fully dollarize countries, the state has ^chosen^ to declare that all debts are payable in dollars (even if it does not have sovereign control over the issue of dollars). In all of the above cases, the state has nevertheless exercised its prerogative to determine what will serve as 'definitive' money.
   What, then, is the purpose of legal tender laws? Davidson provides the answer: legal tender laws determine that which will be 'universally acceptableㅡ^in the eyes of the court^ㅡin the discharge of contractual obligation' (2002: 75, emphasis added).  Therefore, legal tender laws only ensure that when a dispute is settled by the courts in terms of dollars (for example), dollars must be accepted.

  Money is indeed a creature of lawㅡnot legal tender law, but law which imposes and enforces non-reciprocal obligations on the population.  The 'money-thing' is only the empirical manifestation of the state's choice of the 'money of account' that extinguishes these obligations.  This is the nature of the tax-driven money mechanism.

   This chapter began by outlining several broad and specific propositions of Chartalism.  Thus far, the focus has been primarily on the former.  The role of the public authority and taxation was used to decipher the nature of money as a creature of the state and to locate its position in the topmost strata of social debt relations.  The contrast with the Metallist story revealed the importance of distinguishing between the 'money-thing' and the 'money of account'.  Finally it was shown that the chartality of money stems not from legal tender laws but from the state's ability to create the promise of last resort.

  What light, then does Chartalism shed on money in the modern world and specifically on government fiscal and monetary operations?  The remainder of this chapter concentrates on the specific propositions of neo-Chartalism and their applications to policy.


6. Money in the modern world 

Neo-Chartalists are particularly concerned with sovereign currenciesㅡthose inconvertible into gold or any foreign currency through fixed exchange rate (Mosler 1997-98; Wray 2001).  The main point of departure is that most modern economies operate on the basis of high-powered money (HPM) systems. HPMㅡreserves, coins, federal notes and Treasury chequesis that which settles tax obligations and sits at the top of the debt pyramid.  Accordingly, it is also the money ‘into which bank liabilities are converted’ and which is used for clearing the bank community (between banks themselves or between private banks and the central bank) (Wray 1998: 77).  Only a proper understanding of how HPM is supplied through the economy and its effect on the monetary system can lay bare the full implications of modern fiscal and monetary policy.

   Modern money is state money.[:]
  • Taxation today functions to create demand for state currencies in order for the money-issuing authority to purchase requisite goods and services from the private sector.  
  • Taxation, in a sense, is a vehicle for moving resources from the private to the public domain.  
  • Government spending in sovereign currency systems is not limited by the ability of the state to ‘raise’ revenue.  In fact as it will be explained below, sovereign governments face no operational financial constraints.
   To fully grasp the logic of sovereign financing, one must make the analytic distinction between the government and non-government sectors.[:]
  • For the private sector, spending is indeed restricted by its capacity to earn revenue or to borrow.  
  • This is not the case for the public sector, which ‘finances’ its expenditures in its own money.  This is a reflection of its singular supplier (monopoly) status.  
  • For example, in the USA, the dollar is not a ‘limited resource of the government’ (Mosler 1997-98: 169).  Rather it is a tax credit to the population, which is confined with a dollar-denominated tax liability.  
Thus government spending provides to the population that which is necessary to pay taxes (dollars). The government need not collect taxes in order to spend; rather it is the private sector, which must earn dollars to settle its tax debt.  The consolidated government (including the Treasury and the central bank) is never revenue constrained in its own currency.

   If the purpose of taxation is to create demand for state money, then logically and operationally, tax collections cannot occur before the government has provided that which it demands for payment of taxes.  In other words, spending comes first and taxation follows later.  Another way of seeing this causality is to say that government spending 'finances' private sector 'tax payments' and not vice versa.  Several other implications follow.

Deficits and surpluses

Government spending supplies high-powered money to the population.  If the private sector wishes to hoard some of itㅡa normal condition of the systemㅡdeficits necessarily result as a matter of accounting logic.[n10]  Furthermore, the government cannot collet more in taxes than it has previously spend; thus balanced budgets are the theoretical minimum that can be achieved.  But the private sector's desire to net save ensures that deficits are generated.  The market demand for currency, therefore, determines the size of the deficit (Wray 1998: 77-80).
[n10] Godley (1999) has demonstrated that, by accounting necessity, public sector deficits equal private sector surpluses (including those of firms, households and foreigners). CF. Godley, W. (1999), ‘Seven unsustainable processes’, Special Report, Levy Economics Institute. CF. Godley, W. (1996), ‘Money, Finance and National Income Determination: An Integrated Approach’, Levy Economics Institute, Working Paper 167, June.
   In a given year, of course, surpluses are possible, but they are always limited by the amount of deficit spending in previous years.  If during the accounting period government spending falls short of tax collections, private sector holdings of net financial assets necessarily decline.  The implication is that surpluses always reduce private sector net savings, while deficits replenish them.  It should also be noted that, when governments run surpluses, they do not 'get' anything because tax collections 'destroy' high-powered money (Mitchell and Mosler, 2005: 9). To understand this, a closer look at government spending and taxing operations is necessary.

Government spending and taxation

There is no great mystery behind government spending and taxation.  The government spends simply by writing Treasury cheques or by crediting private bank accounts.  Conversely, when the Treasury receives a cheque for tax payment, it debits the commerical bank account on which the cheque was drawn.  At present, it is not necessary to distinguish between the Federal Reserve and the Treasury when discussing government outlays and receipts.  The reason is that when the Treasury writes a cheque drawn on its account at the Fed, it effectively writes a claim on itself.  As Bell and Wray(2002-3) note, intergovernmental balance sheet activity is of little consequence, because it has no impact on the reserve level of the banking system as a whole (p. 264).  What is important, however, is that the consolidated actions of the Fed and the Treasury result in an immediate change in the system-wide level of reserves.  It is this effect on reserves that matters for understanding policy.

   Government fiscal policy is one of two important factors that change the level of reserve balances in the banking system.  The other is through Fed open market operations.  The Treasury is the main supplier of HPM. When it writes a cheque on its account at the Fed, by accounting necessity, reserve balances in the banking system increase.  When it collects tax payments, on the other hand, bank reserves decline. Alternatively, when the Fed buys bonds in the open market, it adds reserves, and when it sells bonds, it drains them.  What Chartalism makes clear next is that the effect of fiscal policy on reserve balances can be large and disruptive.  Thus, while Treasury operations are discretionary, central bank operations are largely defensive in nature.

High-powered money, borrowing and interest rates

Historically banks have aimed to minimize non-interest-bearing reserve balances.  Essentially, reserves in excess of what is necessary to meet daily payment commitments are lent in the overnight market to earn interest.  Alternatively, if bank cannot meet reserve requirements, they will borrow reserves in the overnight market.  All else equal, these operations do not change the level of reserves in the banking system as a whole.  Government spending and taxation, however, do.  Any new injection of 'outside money' (HPM) floods the banking system with excess reserves.  Banks try to pass the unwanted reserves and they only depress overnight interest rates.  Government spending, therefore, increase system-wide reserves and exerts a downward pressure on interest rates.

   Alternatively, the collection of tax revenue reduces high-powered money, i.e. reserves are destroyed.  Since required reserve ratios are computed with a lag (^even^ in a contemporaneous accounting system [see Wray 1998: 102-4), all else equal, tax payments cause a system-wide deficiency of reserves.  The reserve effect is the opposite and, as banks scramble to obtain the necessary reserves in the overnight market, the federal funds rate is bid up above its target rate.  In sum, discretionary Treasury action directly influences overnight interest rates through its impact on reserves.

   The government has devised various ways for mitigating the reserve effect of fiscal policy.  The first ^modus operandi^ is the utilization of tax and loan accounts (T&Ls), which offer only temporary relief to these considerable reserve fluctuations (see Bell 2000 for detailed analysis).  While T&Ls reduces the reserve impact of government spending, the calls on these accounts never match the exact amount of tax collections or government spending.  Therefore, there is ^always^ a flux in reserves in the banking system as a whole that must be offset in order to avoid swings in the overnight interest rate (ibid.).

   The second method for dealing with the excess or deficiency in reserve balances is through open market operations.  To drain the infusion of excess reserves, the Fed offers bonds for sale in the open market. With this action it effectively provides an interest-bearing alternative to banks' interest-free excess reserves and prevents the overnight interest rate from falling to its logical zero-bid limit.[n11] Bond purchases, conversely, add reserves when there is a system-wide reserve deficiency and thus relieve any upward pressure on the overnight rate.  Therefore, open market operations are more appropriately viewed, not as borrowing or lending procedures of the government, but as interest rate maintenance operations.
[n11] For technical discussion of Fed operations, see Fullwiler (2003, 2005)─ Fullwiler, S.T. (2003), 'Timeliness and the Fed's daily tactics', JEI 37(4). ______(2005), 'Paying interest on reserve balances: it's more significant than you think', JEI 39(2).
   From here, several considerations emerge.  First, coordinating activities between the Treasury and the Fed notwithstanding, it is clear that fiscal policy is discretionary and has a significant impact on reserve balances. Second, in an era of positive interest rate policy, the Fed has no choice but to act defensively to offset these reserve fluctuations via open market operations. Thus the Fed largely operates in a non-discretionary manner (Wray 1998; Fullwiler 2003).

   Both taxation and borrowing deplete reserves.  Taxatin simply destroys them, while borrowing drains them by exchanging uncompensated private sector (excess reserves) with interest-bearing ones (bonds).  Taxation and borrowing are not financing operatins for the government but they do affect ^private^ sector nominal wealth.  The former simply reduces 'outside money' (i.e. private sector net saving) while the latter exchanges one asset for another, leaving wealth 'intact' (Wray 2003a: 151).

   All of the above completely reverses conventional wisdom.  Governments do not need the public's money to spend; rather the public needs the government's money to pay taxes.  Government spending always creates new money, while taxation always destroys it.  Spending and taxing are two independent operations. Taxes are not stockpiled and cannot be respent in order to 'finance' future expenditures.  Finally, bond sales are necessary to drain excess reserves generated by fiscal operations in order to maintain a positive interest rate.

The value of the currency and exogenous pricing

Because monetary policy is accommodative and fiscal policy is discretionary, Chartalism assigns the responsibility for maintaining the value of the currency to the latter.  It was already shown that taxes impart value to government money.  As Innes stressed: 'A dollar of money is a dollar, not because of the material of which it is made, but because of the dollar of tax which is imposed to redeem it' (1914: 165).  But he also argued that 'the more government money there is in circulation, the poorer we are' (ibid.: 161). In other words, if government money in circulation far exceeds the total tax liability, the value of the currency will fall. So it is not only the ^requirement^ to pay taxes, but also the ^difficulty^ of obtaining that which is necessary for payment of taxes, that give money its value.

   For example, in discussing the experience of American colonies with inconvertible paper money, Smith recognized that excessive issue relative to taxation was the key to why some currencies maintained their value while others did not (for details see Wray 1998: 21-2).  Wray explains: 'it is the acceptance of the paper money in payment of taxes and the restriction of the issue in relation to the total tax liability that gives value to the paper money' (ibid.: 23).

   This important relationship between leakages and injections of HPM, however, is difficult to gauge.  Chartalists argue that, since the currency is a public monopoly, the government has at its disposal a direct way of determining its value.  Recall that for Knapp payments with chartal money measure a certain number of units of value.  For example, if the state required that to obtain one unit of HPM, a person must supply one hour of labour, then money will be worth exactly thatㅡone hour of labour (Wray 2993b: 104).  Thus, as a monopoly issuer of the currency, the state can determine what money will be worth by setting 'unilaterally the terms of exchange that it will offer to those seeking its currency' (Mosler and Forstater, 1999: 174) [n12]
[n12] Wray notes: 'If the state simply handed HPM on request, its value would be close to zero as anyone could meet her tax liability simply by requesting HPM' (2003b: 104)
   What this means is that the state as a monopoly supplier of HPM has the power to exogenously set the price which it will provide HPM, i.e. the price at which it buys assets, goods and services from the private sector.  While it is hardly desirable for the state to set the prices of all goods and services it purchases, it none the less has this prerogative.  As it will be discussed later, Chartalists recognize that the money monopolist need only set one price to anchor the value of its currency.

   Lastly, Chartalists points out that it is not necessary to force slack on the economy (as espoused by traditional economists) in order to maintain the purchasing power of the currency.  Rather full employment policies, if properly implemented, can do the job (Wray 2003a: 16).

Unemployment

Once again, government deficit spending necessarily result in increased private sector holdings of net financial assets.  If the non-government sector chronically desires to save more than it invests, the result will be a widening demand gap (Wrary 1998: 83).  This demand gap cannot be filled by other private sector agents, because in order for some people to increase their holdings of net savings, other must reduce theirs.  In the aggregate, an increase in the desire to net save can only be accommodated by an increase in government deficit spending. Mosler explains:
Unemployment occurs when, in aggregate, the private sector wants to work and earn the monetary unit of account, but does not want to spend all it would earn (if full employed) on the current products of industry ... Involuntary unemployment is evidence that the desired holding of net financial assets of the private sector exceeds the actual [net savings] allowed by government fiscal policy. (Mosler 1997-98: 176-7)
Similarly, Wray concludes that 'unemployment is de facto evidence that the government's deficit is too low to provide the level of net saving desired'. In a sense unemployment keeps the value of the currency, because it is a reflection of a position where the 'government has kept the supply of fiat money too scarce' (1998: 84).

   For Chartalist it is not necessary to use unemployment to fight inflation.  Rather they advance a full employment policy in which the state exogenously sets one important price in the economy, which in turn serves as stabilization anchor for all other prices (ibid.: 3-10).  This proposal rests on the recognition that the state does not face operational financial constraints, that unemployment is a result of restricting the issue of the currency, and that the state can exercise exogenous pricing.

   But before explaining this proposal, it is important to point out that Chartalist propositions are not ^necessarily^ tied to any particular policy prescription; they are simply a way of understanding the state's powers and liabilities and its financing and pricing options.

   The above implications of Chartalism outline the essential causal government powers regardless of whether they are exercised or not.  Many governments willingly restrict the issue of the currency by balancing budgets.  This in no way indicates that they actually face operational financial constraints.  These are self-imposed, perhaps subject to political or ideological constraints.  Governments furthermore do not explicitly employ their prerogative to set prices, even though they can.  The value of the currency fluctuates, but this does not mean that states cannot devise a mechanism that serves as an anchor for the currency's value.  Chartalism simply delivers the important implications of sovereign currency control that illuminate policy choices.


7. Policy extensions

After disclosing the nature of government finance, Chartalists argue that governments can and should implement 'functional finance'.  The latter was proposed by the late Abba Lerner, who vigorously objected to any conventional ideas about what constitutes 'sound' finance.

   Functional finance can be subsumed under the Chartalist approach, because it appropriately recognizes money as an creature of the state and attributes two important policy roles to government.  Lerner (1947) argued that the state, by virtue of its discretionary power to create and destroy money, has the obligation to keep its spending that maintains (1) the value of the currency and (2) the full employment level of demand for current output.

   For the government to achieve its two main objectives, Lerner proposed two principles of functional finance, which inform decisions on the requisite amount of government spending and the manner of financing it.  More specifically, the first principle provides that total government spending should be 'neither greater nor less than that rate which at the current prices would buy all the goods that is possible to produce' (1943: 39).  Spending below this level results in unemployment, while spending above it causes inflation.  The goal is to keep spending always at the 'right' level in order to ensure full employment and price stability.  The second principle states that government spending should be 'financed' through the issue of new currency.  This second 'law' of functional finance is based on Lerner's recognition that taxation does not finance spending but instead reduces private sector money hoards (ibid.: pp. 40-41).

   Functional finance can be implemented in any country in which the government provides the domestic currency (Wray 2003a: 145).  Two policies, virtually identical in design, that embrace the functional finance approach are the employer of the last resort (ELR) (Mosler 1997-98; Wray 1998) and the buffer stock employment model (MItchell 1998).  These policy prescriptions aim to stabilize the value of the currency by simultaneously eliminating unemployment.  The proposals are motivated by the recognition that sovereign states have no operational financial constraint, can discretionarily set one important price in the economy, and can provide an infinitely elastic demand for labour.

   Chartalists have advocated such employment programmes base on the work of Hyman Minsky and Abba Lerner and which recall the New Deal experience in the USA. The employer of last resort (to use Minsky's terminology) is very simply a government programme that offers a job at a fixed wage/benefits package to anyone who has not found employment in the private sector but is ready, willing and able to work.

   The ELR is proposed as a universal programme without any means tests, thereby providing an infinitely elastic demand for labour by definition.  It eliminates unemployment by offering a job to anyone who wants one.  Through the ELR, the government sets only the price of public sector labour, allowing all other prices to be determined in the market (Mosler 1997-98: 175).  So long as the ELR wage is fixed, it will provide a sufficiently stable benchmark for the value of the currency (Wray 1998: 131).  As explained above, the value of the currency is determined by what one must do to obtain it, and with ELR in place, it is clear exactly what that is: the value of the currency is equal to one hour of ELR work at the going ELR wage.

   Furthermore, it is argued that ELR enhances price stability because of its buffer stock mechanism (Mitchell 1998).  In a nutshell, when recessions hit, jobless workers find employment in the public sector at the ELR wage.  Total government spending rises to relieve deflationary pressures.  Alternatively, when the economy heats up and non-government demand for labour increases, ELR workers are hired into private sector jobs at a premium over the ELR wage.  Government spending automatically contracts, relieving the inflationary pressures in the economy.  Thus, public sector employment acts as a buffer stock that shrinks and expands counter-cyclically.  The buffer stock mechanism ensures that government spending is (as Lerner instructed) always at the 'right' level.

   This proposal innovatively suggests that full employment can anchor the value of the currency (quite contrary to the conventional belief that unemployment is necessary to curb inflation).  The ELR programme utilizes the logical extensions of chartal money to achieve the two goals of governmentㅡthe elimination of unemployment and the stabilization of prices.

   Space does not permit a detailed discussion of this proposal; what is important is to emphasize its chartal institutional features.  The ELR/buffer stock approach recognizes that:

1. The government is the only institution that can divorce 'the offer of labour from the profitability of hiring worker' (Minsky 1986: 308) and can thus provide an infinitely elastic demand for labour, without concerns about financing.

2. The government can formulate an anchor for the value of its currency by exogenously fixing the wage of ELR workers.

3. The government can utilize a buffer stock mechanism to ensure that spending is always at the right levelㅡneither more, nor less.

4. The responsibility for full employment and price stability rests with the Treasury, not the Fed.  'Sound finance' assumes a whole new meaning: it is that which secures full employment and price stability.

Chartalists stress that such an employment programme is a policy option only for countries with sovereign control over their currencies.  It is not a viable proposal for nations that have dollarized or operate under currrency boards or the fixed exchange rate regimes.  This is because the important link between the money-issuing authority and the fiscal agent has been severed, thereby drastically reducing the range of available stability policy options.  Goodhart has pointed out, similarly, the present institutional design of the European Monetary Union exhibits an 'unprecedented divorces between the main monetary and fiscal authorities' (1998: 410).  Kregel (1999) has advanced an innovative proposal to correct for this institutional flaw and allow the EMU to implement an ELR-type of programme.  He recommends that the European Central Bank act as the fiscal agent for the Euro-zone as a whole and implement functional finance to secure high employment and price stability.

   Chartalist analysis can equally be applied to the study of contemporary domestic issues, such as the provision of universal retirement, healthcare and education.  The present debate on the social security 'crisis' in the USA, for example, and virtually the entire rhetoric on government buedgeting, rest on fictitious belief concerning spending limitations.  Chartalism insists that focus on non-exstent problems disables adequate policy responses to pressing issues such as economic growth, development, and currency and price stability.  Only after we abstract from conjured obstacles to fiscal policy can we begin to address problems relating to the provision of adequate healthcare and education, viable employment opportunities, and requisite goods and services for the ageing population.


8. Conclusion

This chapter began with the broad and specific propositions of Chartalism.  These constructively illuminate the tax-driven nature of money and the sovereign powers of monden states.  While Chartalism is not wedded to a singly policy proposal, it logically identifies functional finance as a viable tool for economic stabilization.  Chartal insights can be applied to many different areas, from understanding various currency regimes to such issues as social security and unemployment.  Chartalism is especially suited for studying contemporary monetary and fiscal policy.

   In closing, it is appropriate to recall Lerner's cogent observation that 'The problem of money cannot not be separated from the problems of economics generally just as the problems of economics cannot be separated from the larger problems of human prosperity, peace, and survival' (1947: 317).

   Lerner further cautioned that in sovereign currency regimes 'Functional Finance will work no matter who pulls the levers [and that] those who do not use Functional Finance, ... will stand no chance in the long run against other who will' (1943: 51).  Chartalism is capable of contributing constructively to the public debate about viable policy actions in the public's interest.